Universite du Quebec
a Montreal,
Institut des sciences cognitives
Click
here for full daily schedule
Cliquez
ici pour horaire integral
Optional
satellite workshop on Measuring Consciousness
I.
Inaugural Day: Turing, Dennett & Damasio (Friday June 29)
Dan
Dennett
(Tufts) A
Phenomenal Confusion About Access and Consciousnessabstract
video pdf
-- discussion
thread (comments invited)
Mark
Mitton - Mind &
Magic
Turing Film
1: Alan Turing: Code-Breaker
Antonio
Damasio
(USC) Feelings
and Sentienceabstract (video delayed - will be
uploaded later) -- discussion
thread (comments invited) --
II.
Felt
Function (Saturday
June 30)
Joseph
Ledoux (NYU) The
Perplexing Relationship Between
Emotions and Consciousnessabstract
-- discussion
thread (comments invited) -- video
Fernando
Cervero
(McGill) Cellular and Molecular
Mechanisms of Painabstract -- discussion
thread (comments invited) -- video
Phillip
Jackson
(Laval) The Brain Response to the Pain
of Others: Fleeing Versus Caringabstract
discussion
thread (comments invited)
video
Catherine
Tallon-Baudry
(CNRS) Is Consciousness an Executive
Function?abstract -- discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
Turing
Film 2: Le
modele Turing (langue francaise)
David
Edelman (NSI)
The Octopus as a Possible Invertebrate
Model for Consciousness Studiesabstract -- discussion
thread (comments invited) -- view video
+ PDF
simultaneously for talks + figures
III.
Turing Testing Know-How (Sunday
July 1)
Stevan
Harnad
(UQaM) How/Why Explaining the Causal
Role of Consciousness is Hardabstract
-- discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
Inman
Harvey
(Sussex, UK) No Hard Feelings: Why Would
An Evolved Robot Care?abstract -- discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
Ioannis Rekleitis (McGill) Three
Basic Questions in Robotics: New Directionsabstract -- discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
Dario
Floreano
(Lausanne, Switz.) Evolution of Adaptive
Behavior in Autonomous Robotsabstract
-- discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
Turing Film 3: The
Strange Life and Death of Dr. Turing (part 1, part 2)
James Clark (McGill) Attention: Doing
and Feelingabstract -- discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
Michael
Graziano (Princeton) Consciousness and the Attention Schemaabstract -- discussion
thread (comments invited) -- video
IV.
High-Level Know-How (Monday
July 2)
John
Campbell
(Berkeley) What does Visual Experience
Have to do with Visual Science?abstract -- discussion
thread (comments invited) -- video
Patrick
Haggard (UCL,
UK) Volition and Agency: What is it, and
What is it For?abstract -- discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
David
Freedman
(U Chicago) Brain Mechanisms of Visual
Categorization and Decision-Makingabstract -- discussion
thread
(comments
invited) -- video
Shimon
Edelman
(Cornell) Being in Timeabstract
-- discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
Wayne
Sossin
(McGill) Aplysia: If We Understand the
Cellular Mechanisms Underlying Sensation and Learning, What Do We Need
Consciousness for?abstract -- discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
POSTER SESSION I
&
COCKTAILS
[Tuesday July 3: Day
Off]
V.
What's
Feeling For Anyway? (Wednesday
July 4)
Bernard
Baars (NSI) The
biological basis of conscious experience: Global workspace dynamics in
the brainabstract --
discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
Ezequiel
Morsella
(SFSU) The Primary Function of
Consciousness in the Brainabstract --
discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
Roy
Baumeister (FSU)
The Why, What and How of Consciousnessabstract --
discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
Bjorn
Merker
(Sweden) The Brain's Need for Sensory
Consciousness: From Probabilities to Perceptsabstract
-- discussion
thread (comments invited) -- video
Michael
Shadlen
(HHMI) Consciousness as a Decision to
Engageabstract --
discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
VI.
Feelings
and Firings
(Thursday
July 5)
Wolf
Singer (MPI,
Germany) Consciousness: Unity in Time
Rather Than Space?abstract --
discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
Erik
Cook
(McGill) Are Neural Fluctuations in
Cortex Causally Linked to Visual Perception?abstract
-- discussion thread (comments
invited) -- video
Bjorn
Brembs (FU Berlin,
Germany) Behavioral Freedom and Decision-Making in
Flies: Evolutionary precursor of "Free Will"?abstract
-- discussion thread (comments
invited) -- video
Julio
Martinez
(McGill) Voluntary Attention and Working
Memory in The Primate Brain: Recording from Single Cellsabstract --
discussion thread (comments
invited) -- video
Christopher
Pack
(McGill) Vision During
Unconsciousnessabstract --
discussion thread (comments
invited) -- video
Barbara
Finlay
(Cornell) Continuities/Discontinuities
in Vertebrate Brain Evolution and Cognitive Capacities: Implications
for
Consciousness?abstract --
discussion
thread (comments invited) -- video
VII.
Doing
Things Because You Feel Like It (Friday July 6)
Gary
Comstock
(NCSU) Feeling Mattersabstract --
discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
David
Rosenthal (CUNY
Grad) Does Consciousness Have
any Utility?abstract --
discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video
Mark
Balaguer (Cal
State) A Scientifically Reputable
Version of Indeterministic Libertarian Free Willabstract --
discussion
thread (comments invited) --
video-pt1
video-pt2
Adrian Ward (Harvard) Mind Blanking:
When the Stream of Consciousness Runs Dryabstract
-- discussion
thread (comments invited) -- video
(afternoon off)
VIII.
Consciousness and Causality (Saturday
July 7)
Simon
Baron-Cohen
(Cambridge UK) Evolution of Empathyabstract --
discussion thread (commentary
invited) --
video
Alfred Mele (FSU) Do Conscious Decisions Ever Play a Role in Action Production?abstract -- discussion thread (commentary invited) -- video
Hakwan Lau (Columbia) How to study the functions of subjective awareness?abstract -- discussion thread (commentary invited) -- video
Luiz Pessoa (U Maryland) Cognitive-Emotional Interactionsabstract -- discussion thread (commentary invited) -- video
Marthe Kiley-Worthington (EEREC, France) Comparing Elephant and Equine Mental Traits, Subjectivity and Consciousnessabstract -- discussion thread (commentary invited) -- video
Axel Cleermans (ULB, Belgium) Consciousness and Learningabstract -- discussion thread (commentary invited) -- video
SUMMARY &
DISCUSSION, DAY VIII
IX.
Evolutionary Advantages of Felt Functions (Sunday July 8)
Stefano Mancuso (LINV, Italy) Evolution of Plant Intelligenceabstract -- discussion thread (commentary invited) -- TED video -- canceled
Gualtiero
Piccinini (UMO,
St Louis) Is Consciousness a Spandrel?abstract
Jennifer
Mather
(Lethbridge) Evolutionary Pressures and
Cephalopod Consciousnessabstract --
discussion
thread (commentary invited) --
video
Turing Film 4: Alan
Turing: Code-Breaker and AI Pioneer (Jack Copeland)
POSTER
SESSION II
Eva
Jablonka (TAU,
Israel) Evolutionary Origins of
Experiencingabstract --
discussion
thread (commentary invited) -- video
X.
Measuring Consciousness (Monday
July 9)
Alain
Ptito
(McGill) Neural Mechanisms of Blindsight
after Hemispherectomy: Tapping into the Unconsciousabstract --
discussion
thread (commentary invited) --
video
Amir
Shmuel
(McGill) Neurophysiological and
hemodynamic measurements of spontaneous activity and functional
connectivityabstract -- discussion
thread (commentary invited) --
video
Gilles
Plourde
(McGill) General Anesthetics for the
Study Consciousnessabstract -- discussion
thread (commentary invited) --
video
Amir
Raz
(McGill) Hypnosis as Experimental Tool
to Study Metacognition, Causality and Volitionabstract
-- discussion
thread (commentary invited) --
video not available
XI. Closing
Conference
(same day)
John
Searle
(Berkeley) Consciousness and Causalityabstract -- discussion
thread (commentary invited) --
video
XII. Satellite Workshop on
Measuring Consciousness (Tuesday-Thursday,
July 10-12)
1. Functional
connectivity using neuroimaging (organizer: Sarah Lippe, U. Montreal) (July 10 am)
2. Transcranial
stimulation (organizer: Hugo Theoret, U. Montreal) (July 10 pm)
3. Magnetoencephalography
(2) (organizers: Sylvain Baillet, U McGill & Pierre Jolicoeur, U Montreal) (July 11am,pm)
4. Informational
correlates of consciousness using Bubbles (organizer: Frederic Gosselin, U Montreal) (July 12 am)
abstract Dan
Dennett A
Phenomenal Confusion About Access and Consciousness
Abstract: Many
researchers on
consciousness have adopted Ned Block's purported distinction
between "access"
consciousness and 'phenomenal' consciousness (Block, 1995, 2005, 2007),
but in
spite of its evident appeal, it is not a defensible distinction.
Earlier critiques
(Dennett, 1994, 1995, Cohen and Dennett, 2012) have not deterred those
who
favor the distinction, but perhaps one more exposition of the problems
will
break through.
Block,
N. (2005) Two neural correlates of consciousness. Trends Cogn. Sci. 9,
46–52 7
http://web.gc.cuny.edu/cogsci/private/Block-TICS.pdf
Block,
N. (1995) On a confusion about the function of consciousness. Behav.
Brain Sci.
18, 227–287
Block,
N. (2007) Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology
and
neuroscience. Behav. Brain Sci. 30, 481–499
http://andromeda.rutgers.edu/~kbalog/Web%20publications/Block-BBS.pdf
Cohen
and Dennett 2012,
"Consciousness cannot be separated from function," Michael A. Cohen
and Daniel C. Dennett, Trends in Cognitive Sciences, August 2011, Vol.
15, No.
8, pp. 358-64.http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/cohen.pdf
Dennett,
1994, 'Get Real,' Philosophical Topics, special double issue on
Dennett's
philosophy. http://cogprints.org/280/1/getreal.htm
Dennett,
1995, 'The Path Not Taken,' commentary on Block 1995, Behavioral and
Brain
Sciences http://cogprints.org/287/1/blockrvw.htm
abstract Antonio
Damasio
Feelings and Sentience
Abstract: Reflection on relevant research findings,
new and
old, has changed my views on two issues: the origin and nature of
feelings and
the mechanisms behind the construction of the self. The goal of this
talk is to
consider how the human brain needs to be structured and how it needs to
operate
in order for conscious minds to emerge.
Damasio, Antonio (2012) Self
Comes to Mind Constructing the Conscious Brain. Pantheon Books http://www.usc.edu/schools/college/bci/documents/SCTM%20%20final%20front%20to%206%2010901.PDF
Damasio, Antonio; Thomas J.
Grabowski, Hanna Damasio, Daniel Tranel (2012) Persistence of Feelings
and
Sentience after Bilateral Damage of the Insula. Cerebral
Cortex. http://cercor.oxfordjournals.org/content/early/2012/04/03/cercor.bhs077.short
Damasio, Antonio (2011) Neural
Basis of Emotions. Scholarpedia
http://www.scholarpedia.org/article/wiki/index.php?title=Emotion&oldid=85881
Damasio, Antonio; Thomas J.
Grabowski, Antoine Bechara, Hanna Damasio,
Laura L.B.
Ponto, Josef Parvizi and Richard D. Hichwa (2000)
Subcortical and cortical brain activity during the feeling of
self-generated
emotions. nature neuroscience 3 (10): 1049-1056
http://people.hnl.bcm.tmc.edu/jli/reference/32.pdf
abstract Joseph
Ledoux The Perplexing Relationship
Between Emotions and
Consciousness
Abstract: I propose a re-conceptualization
of key phenomena important in the study of emotion—those
phenomena that
reflect functions and circuits related to survival, and that are shared
by
humans and other animals. The approach shifts the focus from questions
about
whether emotions that humans consciously feel are also present in other
animals, and toward questions about the extent to which circuits and
corresponding functions that are present in other animals (survival
circuits
and functions) are also present in humans. Survival circuit functions
are not
causally related to emotional feelings but obviously contribute to
these, at
least indirectly. The survival circuit concept integrates ideas about
emotion,
motivation, reinforcement, and arousal in the effort to understand how
organisms survive and thrive by detecting and responding to challenges
and
opportunities in daily life.
LeDoux J. (2012) Rethinking the
emotional brain. Neuron 73(4): 653-76. http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/22365542 (PDF will be
provided)
abstract Jorge
Armony
Neural Bases of Emotion
Abstract: In this talk I will describe the main
neural
systems and mechanisms involved in the processing of emotional
information,
highlighting the similarities and differences between species (rats,
monkeys
and humans). In addition, I will briefly present findings and
controversies
regarding the interactions between emotion and other cognitive
processes, such
as attention and awareness.
Sergerie, K., Chochol,
C.,& Armony, J.L. (2008). The
role of the amygdala in emotional processing: A quantitative
meta-analysis of
functional neuroimaging studies. Neuroscience&
Biobehavioral Reviews, 32(4), 811-830.
http://www.affective-sciences.org/system/files/page/2087/sergerie_NBR.pdf
Armony, J.L.& LeDoux,
J.E. (2010). Emotional
responses to auditory stimuli. In A. Palmer& A.
Rees (Eds), The Oxford Handbook of Auditory Science: The
Auditory Brain (pp. 479-505). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press http://bit.ly/ArmonyEmotResp
Vuilleumier, P.,&
Pourtois, G. (2007). Distributed and
interactive brain mechanisms during emotion face perception: evidence
from
functional neuroimaging. Neuropsychologia, 45(1), 174-194. http://labnic.unige.ch/nic/papers/PV_GP_NPsia2006.pdf
abstract Fernando
Cervero
Cellular and Molecular Mechanisms of Pain
Abstract: Pain is a sensory and emotional
experience that in humans also has a
strong cognitive component. We can identify the elementary
neurobiological
mechanisms at cellular and molecular level that mediate injury-related
responses of the nervous system, yet the link between these mechanisms
and the
conscious perception of pain remains elusive. The challenge is
precisely to
identify this link.
Cervero, Fernando (2012)
Understanding Pain:
Exploring the Perception of Pain. MIT Press
http://mitpress.mit.edu/catalog/item/default.asp?ttype=2&tid=13007
abstract Phillip
Jackson
The
Brain Response to the Pain of Others: Fleeing Versus Caring
Abstract: The subjective nature of pain
makes its communication from one person who is suffering to another who
is
observing quite a challenge. Accurate perception of others' pain relies
on
different behavioral and neurophysiological mechanisms, which can vary
depending
on individual, relational and contextual factors. This talk will
discuss
evidence showing how the perception of pain in other individuals is
related to
patterns of brain response similar to thosefound when people are in
pain. While
this 'shared representation' of pain, which can automatically trigger
an
aversive response in the observer leading to avoidance, has likely
played a key
role in the species' survival, we posit that other regulatory
mechanisms can
override this response to allow for concern and prosocial behaviour to
emerge
towards the person in pain. This conscious act of empathy has no doubt
contributed to our social nature.
Decety, J. & Jackson, P.L. (2006). A
social
neuroscience perspective on empathy. Current Directions in
Psychological Sciences,
15, 54-58 http://www.sociology.uiowa.edu/nsfworkshop/JournalArticleResources/Decety_Jackson_SocialNeuroscienceEmpathy_2006.pdf
Voisin, J.I.A., Mercier, C., Canizales,
D.L.,
Marcoux, L.-A. & Jackson, P.L. (2011). I am touched by your pain:
Limb-specific modulation of the cortical response to a tactile
stimulation
during pain observation. The Journal of Pain, 12(11), 1182-1189. http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/21911315
Coll, M.P., Gregoire, M., Latimer, M.,
Eugene, F.,
& Jackson, P.L. (2011). Perception of pain in others: implication
for
caregivers. Pain Management, 1(3), 257-265. http://www.futuremedicine.com/doi/abs/10.2217/pmt.11.21
abstract Catherine
Tallon-Baudry Is
Consciousness an Executive Function?
Abstract: In many theories and experiments,
consciousness is
conceived as an executive function, that distributes precise and
detailed
information guiding behavior.
Indeed, the neural mechanisms correlated with consciousness
share a
number of similarities with those involved in executive functions such
as
attention, memory and control, e.g. amplification and selection,
engagement of
fronto-parietal regions, oscillatory synchrony. This apparent
similarity has
been challenged by a number of experimental evidence showing partial or
full
dissociations between the neural correlates of consciousness and the
neural
correlates of other cognitive functions. Those results suggests that,
from a
neural point of view, consciousness may be less executive than
previously
thought. The current brain-as-a-computer metaphor, with neural
mechanisms
designed to support goal-oriented behavior, may therefore be an
insufficient
framework to understand the biological mechanisms underlying
consciousness.
Catherine Tallon-Baudry, C. (2011) On the
Neural
Mechanisms Subserving Consciousness and Attention Frontiers in
Psychology 2:
397.
http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3253412/
abstract
David
Edelman
The
Octopus as a Possible Invertebrate Model for Consciousness Studies
Abstract:
Among all invertebrates,
the coleoid cephalopods—that
group of molluscs which includes octopuses, squid, and
cuttlefish—have
by
far the largest and most elaborate nervous systems. In addition, these
animals
have eyes that in many ways resemble those of vertebrates, albeit with
some notable
differences (e.g., one type of photoreceptor, no retinal ganglia).
Moreover,
the coleoid cephalopods—particularly the octopus—appear
to be
capable of both seeing moving objects such as predators and prey at
reasonably
great distances and executing a variety of adaptive behaviors in
response to
what they see. Such observations suggest: 1) the presence of relatively
sophisticated visual processing, i.e., neural circuitry that can
support dense
visual input; 2) the possible specialization of sub-modal visual areas
in the
central brain, perhaps analogous to the vertebrate case; and 3)
spatiotemporal
properties of memory that would necessarily involve rapid integration
of visual
information into a dynamic 'scene.'
Here, I will argue that, on
neuroanatomical,
neurophysiological, and behavioral grounds, the octopus in particular
represents an excellent model for investigating the possibility of
conscious
states in an invertebrate. In making this argument, I will: 1) lay out
a
working definition for consciousness that may be extended beyond the
vertebrate
case; 2) describe structural and functional properties which may be the
sine
qua non of sensory consciousness; 3) suggest evolutionary trends (e.g.,
the
emergence of complex vision) that may have set the stage for the advent
of
conscious states in a variety of phyla; and 4) discuss my ongoing work
and
offer a 'roadmap' for additional experiments that could lead to a
robust
methodology for the explicit investigation of sensory consciousness in
these,
and perhaps other, invertebrates
Identifying Hallmarks of
Consciousness in
Non-Mammalian Species
http://www.theassc.org/files/assc/Hallmarks_of_consc_in_non-mammal_species_pre.pdf
Criteria
for consciousness in humans and other
mammals
http://www.theassc.org/files/assc/ConCog2004aWeb.pdf
Animal
consciousness: a synthetic approach
http://www.sussex.ac.uk/Users/anils/Papers/EdelmanSethTiNS2009Preprint.pdf
Gerald
Edelman "Wider than the Sky: The
Phenomenal Gift of Consciousness"
http://www.thedivineconspiracy.org/Z5244Q.pdf
Hochner,
Shomrat & Fiorito (2006) The Octopus: A
Model for a Comparative Analysis of the Evolution of Learning and
Memory
Mechanisms Biol. Bull. 210: 308–317
http://www.octopus.huji.ac.il/site/articles/Hochner-2006.pdf
Borrelli
L, Fiorito G (2008) Behavioral analysis of
learning and memory in Cephalopods. In: Menzel R, Byrne J, editors.
Learning
and Memory: A Comprehensive Reference. UK: Elsevier. pp.
605–627. (PDF
will be provided)
abstract Stevan
Harnad
How/Why Explaining the Causal Role of Consciousness
is Hard
Abstract:
There are two things that
cognitive science needs to explain:
(1) How and why organisms can do all the things they can do and (2) how
and why
organisms feel. Explaining doing -- Turing's problem -- has been dubbed
the
"easy" problem (though it's no easier than other problems in
biological science, and we're nowhere near solving it). Explaining
feeling has
been dubbed the "hard" problem. The reason it is hard is that feeling
keeps on turning out to be superfluous in any causal explanation of
doing.
Harnad, Stevan (1995) Why and How We Are
Not
Zombies. Journal of Consciousness Studies 1:164-167. http://cogprints.org/1601/
Harnad, S. (2000) Correlation vs.
Causality: How/Why
the Mind/Body Problem Is Hard. Journal of Consciousness Studies 7(4):
54-61. http://cogprints.org/1617/
Harnad, S. (2008) The Annotation Game: On
Turing
(1950) on Computing, Machinery and Intelligence. In: Epstein, Robert
&
Peters, Grace (Eds.) Parsing the Turing Test: Philosophical and
Methodological
Issues in the Quest for the Thinking Computer. Springer
http://eprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/7741/
Harnad, S. (2011) Minds, Brains and
Turing.
Consciousness Online 3. http://eprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/22242/
Harnad, S. (2011) Doing, Feeling, Meaning
And
Explaining. In: On the Human. http://eprints.ecs.soton.ac.uk/22243/
Turing, A. M. (1950) Computing Machinery
and
Intelligence. Mind 49:433-460.
abstract Inman
Harvey No
Hard Feelings: Why Would An Evolved Robot Care?
Abstract: When
studying cognition and consciousness, there are three possible
strategies: one
can introspect in an armchair, one can observe natural cognition in the
wild,
or one can synthesise artificial cognition in the lab. Some strands of
Artificial Life pursue the third strategy, and Evolutionary Robotics
opens up a
particular new approach. Whereas most attempts at building AI systems
rely
heavily on designs produced through introspection -- and therefore
reflect the
current fads and intellectual biases of the moment -- the evolutionary
approach
can start from the assumption that we humans are likely
to be hopeless at designing cognitive systems
anything like ourselves. After all, one would not expect a nematode
worm with
just 300 neurons to have much insight into its own cognitive apparatus.
The
evolutionary method does not need the designer, the Watchmaker with
insight.
But it does need clear operational tests for what will count as
cognition --
goal-seeking, learning, memory, awareness (in various objective senses
of that
word), communicating. We can evolve systems with many such cognitive
abilities;
so far to a rather limited extent with proofs of concept, but with no
reason to
expect any barriers in principle to achieving any behaviours that can
be
operationally and objectively defined. Of course, there are no
operational
tests to distinguish a so-called zombie from its human counterpart that
has
feelings, so this seems to leave unresolved the question of whether an
evolved
robot could indeed have subjective feelings.
Harnad
(2011) laid out one version of this issue in a paper entitled "Doing,
Feeling, Meaning and Explaining'", suggesting that the Doing (that can
be
verified operationally) is the Easy part; whereas the Feeling, and
probably by
extension the Meaning are the ineffable and Hard parts. In contrast, I
shall be
focussing on the Explaining, and pointing out that different kinds of
explanations are needed for different jobs. In particular the concept
of
awareness, or consciousness, has a whole range of different meanings
that need
different kinds of explanation. Many of these meanings can indeed be
operationally and objectively defined, and hence we should be able to
build or
evolve robots with these properties. But one crucial sense is
subjective rather
than objective, and cannot be treated in similar fashion. This is a
linguistic
issue to be dissolved rather than a technical problem to be solved.
Harvey,
I., (2002): Evolving Robot Consciousness: The Easy Problems and the
Rest. In
Evolving Consciousness, J.H. Fetzer (ed.), Advances in Consciousness
Research
Series, John Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp. 205 -219.
http://www.sussex.ac.uk/Users/inmanh/consc.pdf
Harvey,
I., (2000): Robotics: Philosophy of Mind using a Screwdriver
In
Evolutionary Robotics: From
Intelligent Robots to Artificial Life, Vol. III, T. Gomi (ed), AAI
Books,
Ontario, Canada, 2000. pp. 207-230. ISBN 0-9698872-3-X.
http://www.sussex.ac.uk/Users/inmanh/screwdriver.pdf
Harvey,
I., Di Paolo, E., Wood, R., Quinn, M, and E. A., Tuci, (2005). Evolutionary Robotics: A new
scientific tool for studying cognition Artificial Life, 11(1-2), pp.
79-98.
http://www.sussex.ac.uk/Users/inmanh/IISREEC-to_press.pdf
abstract Ioannis Rekleitis Three Basic Questions in Robotics: New
Directions
Abstract: Three
basic questions have generated most of the robotics research interest
to date:
Where am I? (Localization) What does the world look like? (Mapping) How to go from A to B? (Path planning)
I
will
examine several answers, identifying common themes. Where? and what?
concern
understanding the world and the robot's place in it: the Simultaneous
Localization and Mapping (SLAM) problems. Localization generalizes to
knowing
about oneself, while mapping generalizes to knowledge representation,
touching
several fields. Solutions are based on both parametric and sample based
strategies. Path planning is interesting, both theoretically and
experimentally. I will review analytical solutions and randomized
strategies
from a historical perspective together with examples of current
systems.
Until
recently robotics was trying to understand the world. Current and
future
research is more concerned with changing it. The problem of
manipulating and
grasping has gained prominence in the last few years. In the past,
robots were
concerned with moving through the environment, avoiding contact, and
constructing models. Today, robots approach objects, use contact, and
moderate
forces to understand and modify the world.
Dupuis,
E; R L'Archeveque, P Allard, I Rekleitis and E Martin (2005) Toward
Fully
Autonomous Robotics Operation Framework.In: Ayanna
Howard and Eddie Tunstel (eds.) Intelligence for
Space Robotics TSI Press, pp 217-234,
Rekleitis,
IM, Dudek, G & Evangelos M (2001) Multi-Robot Collaboration for
Robust
Exploration. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence 31: 7-40
http://www.cim.mcgill.ca/~yiannis/Publications/journal.pdf
abstract Dario
Floreano
Evolution of Adaptive Behavior in Autonomous Robots
Abstract: A
spectacular demonstration of the power of natural selection comes from
experiments in the field of evolutionary robotics, where scientists
have
conduct- ed experimental evolution with robots. Evolutionary robotics
has also
been advocated as a method to automatically generate control systems
that are
comparatively simpler or more efficient than those engineered with
other design
methods because the space of solutions explored by evolution can be
larger and
less constrained than that explored by conventional engineering
methods. In
this talk I will examine key experiments that illustrate how, for
example,
robots whose genes are translated into simple neural networks can
evolve the
ability to navigate, escape predators, coadapt brains and body
morphologies, and
cooperate. We present mostly -- but not only -- experimental results
performed
in our laboratory, which satisfy the following criteria. First, the
experiments
were at least partly carried out with real robots, allowing us to
present a
video showing the behaviours of the evolved robots. Second, the robot's
neural
networks had a simple architecture with no synaptic plasticity, no
ontogenetic
development, and no detailed modelling of ion channels and spike
transmission.
Third, the genomes were directly mapped into the neural network (i.e.,
no
gene-to-gene interaction, time-dependent dynamics, or ontogenetic
plasticity).
By limiting our analysis to these studies we are able to highlight the
strength
of the process of Darwinian selection in comparable simple systems
exposed to
different environmental conditions.
D. Floreano and L. Keller
(2010) Evolution of Adaptive Behaviour in Robots by Means of Darwinian
Selection, in PLOS Biology, vol. 8, num. 1, p. e100029.
http://www.plosbiology.org/article/info%3Adoi%2F10.1371%2Fjournal.pbio.1000292
Harvey I, Di Paolo E, Wood R,
Quinn M, Tuci E (2005) Evolutionary robotics: a new scientific tool for
studying cognition. Artif Life 11: 79-98.
http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/abs/10.1162/1064546053278991
abstract James Clark
Attention: Doing and Feeling
Abstract:
Humans perceive the world
in an active fashion, and process
only a limited subset of the sensory data available to them. Attention
selection mechanisms decide on which parts of the sensory stream to
focus on.
This lecture will consider two threads linking attention and
consciousness. The
first is the finding that the contents of consciousness (feeling)
depend
strongly on what is being attended to, as indicated by the "Change
Blindness" phenomenon. The other thread is the connection between motor
activity (doing) and attention, as espoused by Rizzolati's
"Pre-Motor" Theory of Attention, and embodied consciousness theories,
such as O'Regan's Sensorimotor Contingency Theory. The implications of
the role
of attention on consciousness for the Robotic Turing Test will be
discussed.
Rensink, R.A., O'Regan, J.K.,
and Clark, J.J., ``To See or Not to See: The Need for Attention to
Perceive
Changes in Scenes.'', Psychological Science, Vol 8, pp 368-373. 1997.
http://www.cs.ubc.ca/~tmm/courses/cpsc533c-04-spr/morereadings/PsychSci97-RR.pdf
Clark, J.J., "Spatial
Attention and Latencies of Saccadic Eye Movements", Vision Research,
Vol.
39, No. 3, pp 583-600, 1999
http://www.cim.mcgill.ca/~clark/vmrl/web-content/papers/jjclark_vr_03_1999_draft.pdf
Jie, L. and Clark, J.J., "Video
Game Design Using an Eye Movement Dependent Model of Visual
Attention'', ACM Transactions on Multimedia Computing, Communications,
and
Applications, Vol. 4, No. 3, pp 22:1-16, 2008
http://www.cim.mcgill.ca/~clark/vmrl/web-content/papers/jjclark_TOMCCAP_2008.pdf
Rizzolatti, G. (1983), "Mechanisms
of selective attention in mammals'', in Advances in
Vertebrate
Neuroethology, Ewart, J.P., Capranica, R.R., and Ingle, D.J., (eds.),
Plenum,
New York, pp 261-297
J. K.
O'Regan and A. Noe. A sensorimotor account of vision and visual
consciousness.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24:939-1031, 2001.
http://cogsci.uni-osnabrueck.de/~nbp/PDFs_Publications/ORegan.BBS.01pdf.pdf
abstract Michael
Graziano
Consciousness and the Attention Schema
Abstract:
One possible explanation
of awareness is that it is a
construct of the social perceptual machinery. Humans have specialized
neuronal
machinery that allows us to be socially intelligent. The primary role
for this
machinery is to construct models of other people--minds thereby gaining
some
ability to predict the behavior of other individuals. In the present
hypothesis, specific cortical machinery, notably in the superior
temporal
sulcus and the temporo-parietal junction, is used to build the
construct of
awareness and attribute it to other people. The same cortical
machinery, in
this hypothesis, is also used to attribute awareness to oneself. Damage
to this
cortical machinery can lead to disruptions in consciousness such as
hemispatial
neglect. In this theory, the value of the construct of awareness, and
the value
of attributing it to a person, is to gain a useful predictive model of
that
person--attentional processing. Attention is a style of information
processing
in the brain in which neuronal signals compete. One interrelated set of
signals
rises in strength at the expense of others, and thereby dominates the
control
of behavior. Awareness, in the present hypothesis, is a construct, a
useful
schema, that models the dynamics and essential properties of attention.
To be
aware of X is to construct a model of one--attentional focus on X. A
brain
concludes it is aware of X, and assigns a high degree of certainty to
that
conclusion, and reports that conclusion, because of an informational
model that
depicts awareness of X.
Graziano MSA and Kastner S
(2011) Human consciousness and its relationship to social neuroscience:
A novel
hypothesis. Cognitive Neuroscience, 2: 98-113.
http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3223025/
abstract
John
Campbell
What does Visual Experience Have to do with Visual
Science?
Abstract: The
epistemic role of consciousness in sensory experience. Classically,
vision
science assumed we do not need to appeal to notions relating to sensory
awareness to explain how it is that perception generates knowledge of
our
surroundings. Sensory experience
has often been seen as an epiphenomenon in the generation of knowledge. This is not the view of ordinary
common-sense. Ordinarily, we take
that it is only because we have sensory experience that we can know
what the
objects and properties around us are.
But where would a role for sensory experience fit in an account
of the
production of knowledge? I
approach this question by looking at the contrast Huang and Pashler
(2007) draw
between the roles of visible properties in selecting and in accessing
regions
or objects in the visual field. I
use this to articulate an account of the way in which an externalist
account of
perceptual experience relates to a classical account of visual
computation.
Huang and Pashler, 2007, 'A
Boolean Map Theory of Visual Attention', Psych. Review 114, 599-631. http://www.pashler.com/Articles/Huang_Pashler_PR2007.pdf
Campbell, John, 2011, 'Visual
Attention and the Epistemic Role of Consciousness', in Mole, Smithies
and Wu
(eds.), Attention: Philosophical
and Psychological Essays (Oxford:
OUP), 321-343. [PDF will be provided]
abstract
Patrick
Haggard
Volition and Agency: What is it, and What is it For?
Abstract: Voluntary
actions are often defined as actions that are internally-generated,
rather than
directly triggered by an external stimulus. The
capacity for voluntary action gives control of human
behaviour a 'freedom from immediacy' (Mike Shadlen's term), that other
animals
may lack. But voluntary actions
are also characterised by a special relation with conscious thought. On a classical, rationalist model, we
consciously deliberate, form conscious intentions, and these drive our
actions. The crucial link in this
chain is the transition from mind to body, when an intentions-in-action
is
transformed to a motor command, and a bodily movement.
I will discuss a number of studies of
this process. First, I will
consider whether the experience of being about to act is a direct
readout of
ongoing neural preparation, or a retrospective narrative to explain our
actions
post hoc. I will then ask the same
questions about sense of agency - i.e., the feeling that our actions
cause
events in the outside world. Both
prospective and retrospective components are shown to exist. The retrospective component presumably
aims at providing a coherent and description of our own behaviour and
self-consciousness. The
prospective component is harder to account for, and I will consider two
possible functions. First, being
aware of what we are about to do just before we do it might contribute
to the
control or veto of action. Second, it might improve complex
instrumental
learning. Both accounts suffer
from the normal difficulties of ascribing causal roles to
consciousness, and
the existence of prospective aspects of intention and agency cannot
save
concepts of 'conscious free will'.
Finally, I will consider the implications of recent work on
action
awareness for moral and legal responsibility.
Haggard
P (2008).
Human volition: towards a neuroscience of will.
Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 9,
934-946. http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/19020512
Chambon V, Wenke D, Fleming
D, Prinz W & Haggard P. (in press).
An online neural substrate for sense of agency.
Cerebral Cortex, in press http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/22510529
abstract
David
Freedman
Brain Mechanisms of Visual Categorization and
Decision-Making
Abstract: We have a
remarkable ability to recognize the behavioral significance, or
category
membership of a wide range of visual stimuli. While much is known about
how
simple visual features (such as color, orientation and direction of
motion) are
processed in early stages of the visual system, much less is known
about how
the brain learns and recognizes categorical information that gives
meaning to
incoming stimuli. This talk will review a series of neurophysiological
and
behavioral experiments aimed at understanding the neuronal
representations
underlying visual categorization. We have found that the activity of
individual
neurons in both the posterior parietal and lateral prefrontal cortices
can
reflect the learned category membership of visual stimuli, and that
these two
areas play distinct roles in category-based decision making.
Freedman D.J. and Assad J.A.
Experience-Dependent Representation of Visual Categories in Parietal
Cortex.
Nature, 443: 85-88, 2006. http://www.cns.upf.edu/jclub/freedman_assad2006.pdf
Swaminathan S.K. and Freedman
D.J. Preferential encoding of visual categories in parietal cortex
compared to
prefrontal cortex. Nature Neuroscience, 15: 315-320, 2012. http://monkeylogic.uchicago.edu/Swaminathan_Freedman_nature_neuroscience_2012_with_SuppInfo.pdf
Freedman D.J. and Assad J.A.
A Proposed Common Neural Mechanisms for Categorization and Perceptual
Decisions. Nature Neuroscience, 14:143-146, 2011. http://library.ucls.uchicago.edu/FirstDay201112/learning/categorization%20and%20perceptual%20decisions.pdf
Freedman D.J., Riesenhuber M., Poggio T., and Miller E.K. A Comparison of Primate Prefrontal and Inferior Temporal Cortices During Visual Categorization. Journal of Neuroscience, 23: 5235-5246, 2003. http://www.neuro.cjb.net/content/23/12/5235.full
abstract
Shimon
Edelman
Being in Time
Abstract: Philosophical and computational
considerations, along
with neurobiological data, suggest that phenomenal experience is
holistic in
the sense that it emerges from the dynamics of the entire brain. On
this
account, your experience of the page in front of you (say) is
predicated upon
coordinated activity, not just of visual areas alone, but of the rest
of your
brain as well. Experience thus must be inherently temporally extended,
if only
because coordination requires time. What is the nature of this
coordination and
how much time does it take for experience to emerge? Lessons from the
science
of parallel distributed computation suggest that putting experience --
or, for
that matter, any other collective action such as decision making -- on
hold
until after all of the brain's constituents have had a chance to reach
a
consensus about it is a recipe for permanent functional paralysis. To understand why the brain does not
have to wait for long (let alone indefinitely) to figure out what
experience it
is having, we must note that coordination, like experience that
emerges, is an
ongoing endogenous process modulated by input, rather than a transient
ripple
in an otherwise quiescent medium. Thus, the input-influenced present
turn of the
system's trajectory through the activation space -- the embodiment of
experience -- is shaped collectively by the system's history, which
likely
possesses a variety of natural time scales amenable to empirical
investigation.
Edelman,
S., and T. Fekete, Being in Time, extended
abstract for the poster presented at the 15th meeting of the
Association for
Scientific Study of Consciousness (ASSC15), June 2011, Kyoto, Japan.
http://kybele.psych.cornell.edu/%7Eedelman/Edelman-Fekete-ASSC15-extended-abstract.pdf
abstract
Wayne
Sossin
Aplysia: If We Understand the Cellular Mechanisms Underlying Sensation
and
Learning, What Do We Need Consciousness for?
Abstract: Aplysia
is a model system for defining the relationship between neuronal
plasticity and
behavior. Indeed, many of the circuits underlying Aplysia's simple
behaviors
are understood, as well as how the animal can change those circuits
after
experience. Moreover, it is beginning to be understood how biogenic
amine and
neuropeptide pathways can activate or inhibit distinct motor programs
to bias
the animals decisions on what to do. I will explore, given the limited
number
of neurons in Aplysia, whether the additional pathways are present that
would
lead to the complex feedback systems that are probably required for
consciousness.
Sossin WS. Defining memories
by their distinct molecular traces. Trends Neurosci. 2008
Apr;31(4):170-5. Epub
2008 Mar 10. http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/18329733
Cropper. Neurosignals.http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/15004426# 2004
Jan-Apr;13(1-2):70-86. Feeding
neural networks in the mollusc Aplysia.
Evans
http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed?term=Evans%20CG%5BAuthor%5D&cauthor=true&cauthor_uid=15004426
Hurwitz http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed?term=Hurwitz%20I%5BAuthor%5D&cauthor=true&cauthor_uid=15004426
Jing http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed?term=Jing%20J%5BAuthor%5D&cauthor=true&cauthor_uid=15004426
Proekt http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed?term=Proekt%20A%5BAuthor%5D&cauthor=true&cauthor_uid=15004426
Romero http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed?term=Romero%20A%5BAuthor%5D&cauthor=true&cauthor_uid=15004426
Rosen http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed?term=Rosen%20SC%5BAuthor%5D&cauthor=true&cauthor_uid=15004426 .
Science.http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed?term=Kandel%20dialogue# 2001 Nov
2;294(5544):1030-8. The
molecular biology of memory storage: a dialogue between genes and
synapses.
Feeding behavior of Aplysia:
a model system for comparing cellular mechanisms of classical and
operant
conditioning.http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/17142299 Baxter DA,
Byrne JH. Learn Mem. 2006
Nov-Dec;13(6):669-80. Review.
abstract
Bernard
Baars The
biological basis of conscious experience: Global workspace dynamics in
the brain
Abstract:
Some philosophers maintain
that consciousness as
subjective experience has no biological function. However, conscious
brain
events seem very different from unconscious ones. For example, the
cortex and
thalamus support the reportable qualitative contents of consciousness.
Subcortical structures like the cerebellum do not. Likewise, attended
sensory
stimuli are typically reportable as conscious, while accurate memory
traces of
the same stimuli are not reportable, unless they are specifically
recalled. Like other major
adaptations, conscious and unconscious brain events have distinctive
biological
pros and cons. These involve information processing efficiency,
metabolic
costs, and behavioral pros and cons. The well-known momentary limited
capacity
of conscious contents is an example of an information processing cost,
while
the very large and energy-hungry corticothalamic system makes costly
metabolic
demands. Limited capacity can cause death and injury in humans and
other
animals, as in the case of traffic accidents and predation by ambush.
Sleep is
a state of high vulnerability among prey animals. We can begin to
sketch out
some of the biological costs and benefits of conscious states and their
stream
of reportable contents.
Baars,
B.J. & Gage, N.M. (2011) Fundamentals of Cognitive Neuroscience: A
Beginner's Guide. Elsevier/Academic Press. (See Chapter 8 for the brain
basis
of consciousness and attention.)
Baars,
B.J. (2012) The biological costs of consciousness. Nature Precedings. http://precedings.nature.com/documents/6775/version/1
Edelman,
G.M., J. Gally & B.J. Baars (2011) Biology of consciousness.
Frontiers in
Psychology. January, Vol. 2. http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3111444/
Franklin,
S., S. D� Mello, B. J. Baars & U. Ramamurthy
(2011)
Evolutionary Pressures
for Perceptual Stability and Self as Guides to Machine Consciousness.
Int Jnl
Machine Consciousness. http://www.theassc.org/files/assc/Evolutionary-Pressures-2009.pdf
abstract
Ezequiel
Morsella
The Primary Function of Consciousness in the Brain
Abstract: Despite the challenges in
unraveling how the nervous system gives rise to consciousness, a
consensus has
been growing that (a) consciousness is associated with only a subset of
all
nervous regions and processes, and (b) the primary function of
consciousness is
to integrate processes/information that would otherwise be independent
(the
integration consensus). Recent
research illuminates the subset of areas and processes that are most
closely
related to conscious processing.
These investigations reveal that consciousness serves to
integrate only
certain kinds of information/processes.
Many forms of integration can occur unconsciously.
The peculiar form of integration
associated with consciousness involves a form of information
broadcasting that
is intimately related to what is casually referred to as 'voluntary'
action and
to the skeletal muscle output system.
All these developments are synthesized in Supramodular
Interaction
Theory (SIT). During this lecture,
I will review evidence for the integration consensus, SIT, and other
notable
contemporary reductionistic approaches.
Morsella, E. (2005). The
function of phenomenal states: Supramodular interaction theory.
Psychological
Review, 112, 1000-1021. LINK: http://bss.sfsu.edu/emorsella/images/MorsellaPsychRev.pdf
abstract
Roy
Baumeister
The
Why, What and How of Consciousness
Abstract: Consciousness
is a distinguishing trait of human experience, but does it cause
behavior or
serve other useful functions? Recent critiques, especially from studies
of
automatic processes and brain functions, have suggested that it is
inefficient
and ineffective for controlling action and unnecessary for perceiving
the
environment. This talk reviews experimental studies on how
manipulations of
conscious thought cause changes in behavior. It draws new conclusions
about
what conscious thought can and cannot do -- and what it can do better
than
unconscious processes. It goes on to argue that the core functions of
conscious
thought are for relating to the social and cultural environment.
Baumeister,
Roy F. , E. J. Masicampo, and Kathleen D.
Vohs (2011)
Do
Conscious Thoughts Cause Behavior? Annual Review of Psychology 62:
331-361
http://carlson.umn.edu/assets/165663.pdf
Baumeister,
Roy F. and E. J. Masicampo (2010) Conscious
Thought Is for Facilitating Social and Cultural Interactions: How
Mental
Simulations Serve the Animal–Culture Interface
Psychological Review 117(3)
945–971
http://ambadylab.stanford.edu/ej/BaumeisterMasicampo2010PsychRev.pdf
abstract
Bjorn
Merker The
Brain's Need for Sensory Consciousness: From
Probabilities to Percepts
Abstract: Some
years ago I suggested that consciousness pays its way in the functional
economy
of the brain by unlocking the savings hidden in the mutual dependencies
among
target selection, action selection and motivational ranking through
multi-objective constraint satisfaction among them (Merker 2007, p.
70). This
would place consciousness at a late stage in the brain's operations,
suggesting a
subcortical implementation of key mechanisms of consciousness in sites
of
global convergence in midbrain and diencephalon. No doubt our cortical
machinery is the source of much of our conscious contents, but that
does not
mean that the cortex also must be the site where those contents become
conscious. Recent information-theoretic analyses of the probabilistic
data
format of cortical operations point to the utility of collapsing
cortical
probability density distributions to estimate form in extracortical
locations
(Ma et al. 2006). I propose that this essential step in neural
operations is
implemented in a subcortical "global best estimate buffer" whose
contents - alone among neural activities - are conscious. They are so
not by
virtue of anything being "added" to them in order to "make them
conscious," but as a direct consequence of the format they must adhere
to
in order to provide a global best estimate within the narrow time
constraints
of inter-saccadic intervals. That format directly matches the global
format of
our phenomenal experience, which in its sensory aspects is that of
naive
realism.
Ma,
W.J., Beck, J.M., Latham, P.E. & Pouget, A.
2006. Bayesian inference with probabilistic population codes. Nature
Neuroscience, 9, 1432-1438. http://psych.stanford.edu/~jlm/pdfs/Ma%20et%20al%20with%20figs.pdf
Merker,
B. 2007. Consciousness without a cerebral
cortex: A challenge for neuroscience and medicine. Target article, peer
commentary
and author--response. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30, 63: 134. http://eprint.ncl.ac.uk/file_store/production/87645/626A59CF-2311-4DA6-BFBD-2D4AACC68DD3.pdf
abstract
Paul
Cisek The
Vanishing Central Executive: Distributed Neural
Mechanisms for Decision-Making
Abstract: Modern
theories of the brain describe it as a series of information processing
stages
for perceiving and representing the world, thinking about it, and then
acting
upon it. However, this intuitively appealing and influential view is
not
well-supported by neurophysiological data. Sensory, cognitive, and
motor
functions appear distributed through diverse brain regions and often
mixed
within the activity of individual neurons. As an alternative, I will
describe a
model based on theories from ethology, which suggests that behavior
involves a
continuous competition between potential ways to interact with the
world. I
will present recent results supporting some of the key predictions of
this
alternative way of looking at how the brain implements behavior,
focusing on
neurophysiological studies of decisions between actions.
Cisek,
P. (1999) Beyond the computer metaphor:
Behaviour as interaction. Journal of Consciousness Studies. 6(11-12):
125-142. http://www.cisek.org/pavel/Pubs/Cis1999.pdf
Cisek,
P. and Kalaska, J.F. (2010) Neural mechanisms
for interacting with a world full of action choices. Annual Review of
Neuroscience. 33: 269-298. http://www.cisek.org/pavel/Pubs/CisekKalaska2010.pdf
abstract
Michael
Shadlen
Consciousness as a Decision to Engage
Abstract: Consciousness
encompasses a variety of functions and properties, such as awakening,
awareness, and subjective aspects of both perception and volition
(e.g., qualia
and authorship, respectively). It remains to be seen whether these
diverse
functions are related to one another through common neural mechanisms,
and if
so how. Here, we advance the thesis that the neural mechanisms that
give rise
to conscious states share features with neural mechanisms that underlie
simpler
forms of decisions. The neurobiology of decision-making provides
detailed
insight into how the brain deliberates and reasons from evidence to
make
choices. The underlying mechanisms, mainly studied in animals, could
support a
variety of complex cognitive functions that probably operate
independently of
many aspects of consciousness. For example, many complex decisions in
humans
rely upon wakefulness but not upon awareness or authorship. In animal
studies,
decisions are typically embodied: they can be described as selection
among
possible actions. By substituting 'circuits' for 'actions' in the
preceding
phrase, we generalize from 'deciding to do' to 'deciding to consider'
or, more
generally, 'deciding to decide to. . . .' This is an appealing notion
from the
perspective of brain evolution, because it allows us to recognize
ideation as
an elaboration of a simpler sensory-motor design. We propose that many
of the
functions of consciousness are simply ways of engaging the environment.
Thus
consciousness might be mediated by (non-conscious) decisions to engage,
as in
awakening, or to engage in a certain way, as when attaching narrative
to
action. Although the neural mechanisms underlying 'decisions to engage'
are
unknown, they are likely to involve intralaminar (and matrix) thalamus
and
processes that 'decide' to turn other circuits on. This idea invites an
analogy
between the functions of brain regions that project to matrix thalamus,
including the 'default system', and the role of parietal cortex in
perceptual
decisions. While highly speculative, we think 'decision to engage'
provides a
biologically plausible and computationally coherent hypothesis about
the neural
correlates of consciousness. (From
Shadlen & Kiani 2011)
Shadlen
MN, Roskies AL. 2012. The Neurobiology of
Decision-Making and Responsibility: Reconciling Mechanism and
Mindedness.
Frontiers in Neuroscience 6 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3332233/
Shadlen
MN, Kiani R. 2011. Consciousness as a decision
to engage. In Characterizing Consciousness: From Cognition to the
Clinic?
Research and Perspectives in Neurosciences, ed. S Dehaene, Y Christen,
pp.
27-46. Berlin Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag
http://www.shadlen.org/~mike/papers/mine/Shadlen2011.pdf
Shadlen
MN, Kiani R, Hanks TD, Churchland AK. 2008.
Neurobiology of Decision Making: An Intentional Framework. In Better
Than
Conscious?: Decision Making, the Human Mind, and Implications for
Institutions,
ed. C Engel, W Singer, pp. 71-102. Cambridge: MIT Press
http://www.shadlen.org/pmwiki/uploads/Science/Intentional_Framework.pdf
Gold
J, Shadlen MN. 2007. The neural basis of decision
making. Annu Rev Neurosci 30:535-74 http://arjournals.annualreviews.org/eprint/JUj7dUJvjUWqeGwIFqzV/full/10.1146/annurev.neuro.29.051605.113038
Kiani
R, Shadlen MN. 2009. Representation of confidence
associated with a decision by neurons in the parietal cortex. Science
324:759-64
http://www.shadlen.org/~mike/papers/mine/KianiScience2009.pdf
Yang
T, Shadlen MN. 2007. Probabilistic reasoning by
neurons. Nature 447:1075-80
http://www.shadlen.org/pmwiki/uploads/Science/yang_shadlen_2007.pdf
Shadlen
MN, Movshon JA. 1999. Synchrony unbound: a
critical evaluation of the temporal binding hypothesis. Neuron 24:67-77
http://www.shadlen.org/~mike/papers/mine/shadlen_movshon1999.pdf
abstract
Wolf
Singer
Consciousness: Unity in Time Rather Than Space?
Abstract: The
search for neuronal correlates of consciousness (NCC) often relies on
comparisons between neuronal activation patterns associated with
conscious and
non-conscious processing, respectively, of physically identical
stimuli. This
strategy is known as the subtraction method and thought to isolate
neuronal
processes specific for conscious experience. However, this approach
does not
allow one to clearly separate the NCC proper from processes that just
permit
access to consciousness such as fluctuations in excitability at early
stages or
from processes that follow conscious experience such as storage of
perceived
items in working memory and response preparation. This problem can be
reduced
but not eliminated by considering the precise temporal sequence of
events,
using methods that capture brain activity with high temporal resolution
such as
time frequency analysis and event related potentials extracted from EEG
or MEG
signals.
Applying these methods we
find as an early NCC a brief burst of oscillatory activity in the
beta/gamma
frequency range that occurs about 180 ms after stimulus presentation
and is
synchronized across a widely distributed network of cortical areas.
This
suggests as NCC not the activation of a particular, higher order
cortical area
but a dynamic state that is characterized by the coherent activation of
a
widely distributed network. This agrees with Baars and Dehaene's
hypothesis of
a work space and also with Sherrington's view that the unity of
conscious
experience does not require convergence in space (anatomical
convergence) but
results from coherence in time (temporal convergence, phase coherence).
Indications for a special role of precisely synchronized oscillatory
responses
in the high frequency range have been obtained previously in animal
experiments, using the paradigm of binocular rivalry.
Fries,
P., Roelfsema, P.R., Engel, A.K., Koenig, P., and
Singer, W. (1997) Synchronization of oscillatory responses in visual
cortex
correlates with perception in interocular rivalry. Proceedings of the
National
Academy of Sciences of America. 94(23), 12699-12704 http://www.pnas.org/content/94/23/12699.full.pdf+html
Singer,
W. (1998) Consciousness and the structure of
neuronal representations. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B 353: 1829-1840 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1692413/pdf/9854255.pdf
Engel,
A.K., P. Fries, P.Koenig, M. Brecht, and W.
Singer (1999) Temporal binding, binocular rivalry, and consciousness.
Consciousness and Cognition 8: 128-151 http://www.ini.ethz.ch/~peterk/OwnPapers/engel.cc.99.pdf
Engel,
A.K., P. Fries, P. Koenig, M. Brecht, and W. Singer
(1999) Concluding Commentary. Does time help to understand
consciousness?
Consciousness and Cognition 8: 260-268
Melloni,
L., C. Molina, M. Pena, D. Torres, W. Singer,
and E. Rodriguez (2007) Synchronization of neural activity across
cortical areas
correlates with conscious perception. The Journal of Neuroscience
27(11):
2858-2865 http://www.jneurosci.org/content/27/11/2858.full.pdf+html
Melloni,
L. and W. Singer (2010) Distinct
characteristics of conscious experience are met by large-scale neuronal
synchronization. In: E. Perry, D. Collerton, F. LeBeau and H. Ashton
(Eds.).
New Horizons in the Neuroscience of Consciousness. Advances in
Consciousness
Research 79. John Benjamins, B.V., Amsterdam 2010, 17-28
Aru,
J., T. Bachmann, W. Singer and L. Melloni (2012)
Distilling the neural correlates of consciousness. Neuroscience and
Biobehavioral Reviews 36(2): 737-746
abstract
Erik
Cook Are Neural Fluctuations in Cortex
Causally Linked to Visual Perception?
Abstract: Our
perception fluctuates when we view images at the threshold of our
visual
capabilities. It has been widely
shown that fluctuations in visual cortical activity are correlated with
fluctuations in perception. The
source of these neural fluctuations, however, is not clear. Are they causal, such as bottom-up
sensory noise, that directly influences perception? Or are these
fluctuations
non-causal, such as top-down attentional modulation, that produce
correlations
between sensory neural activity and perception when no functional link
actually
exists between the two? In this
presentation, I will present accumulating evidence that both causal and
non-causal processes are responsible for this functional link and that
careful
electrophysiological observations can distinguish between these two
sources of
neural fluctuations.
Smith,
J.E., Zhan, C.A. and Cook, E.P. The
functional link between area MT
neural fluctuations and detection of a brief motion stimulus. Journal of Neuroscience 31: 13458 - 68,
2011. http://www.jneurosci.org/content/31/38/13458.long
abstract
Bjorn
Brembs
Behavioral Freedom and Decision-Making in Flies:
Evolutionary precursor of "Free Will"?
Abstract: The collaborative actions of chance and
necessity make
up the foundation of evolutionary success: the deterministic rules of
selection
act upon the stochastic genetic variation to bring about adaptive
change.
Genetics studies both the variability of genomes and the almost
faithful
transmission of genetic information from generation to generation. The
same
concerted action of chance and necessity underlies bacterial
chemotaxis:
Escherichia coli uses straight runs and random tumbles to orient in
odor
plumes. In both instances, we understand both the mechanisms underlying
the
generation of variability and those of the the deterministic
components. The
behavior of organisms with nervous systems also employs this powerful
combination when at first different behaviors are tried out in a new
situation
until the desired goal is achieved. Subsequent encounters with the same
situation then lead to the successful behavior increasingly quickly.
While we
understand the deterministic selection processes ('reinforcement')
leading to
the reliable production of the behavior comparatively well, we know
next to
nothing about how the behavioral variability is generated that provides
the
substrate for these selection processes to act upon. Mutation, sexual
recombination, jumping genes or horizontal gene transfer are crucial
not only
for evolution to take place, these fundamentally stochastic processes
also make
evolution principally unpredictable. Analogously, the processes by
which brains
generate variable and sometimes genuinely new behaviors are crucial for
brains
to generate adaptive behavioral choice and make brains principally
unpredictable. It is this unpredictability which forms the evolutionary
basis
for behavioral freedom, a candidate for the evolutionary precursor to
what we
today call 'free will' in humans.
Brembs
2010 Towards a scientific concept of free will as
a biological trait: spontaneous actions and decision-making in
invertebrates. Proc
Roy Soc B http://rspb.royalsocietypublishing.org/content/early/2010/12/14/rspb.2010.2325
Brembs
(2008) The Importance of Being Active J.
Neurogenetics
http://bjoern.brembs.net/request79.html
Grobstein,
Variability in Brain Function and Behavior
http://serendip.brynmawr.edu/bb/EncyHumBehav.html
Miller,
Protean Primates: The Evolution of Adaptive
Unpredictability
in Competition and Courtship http://www.unm.edu/~psych/faculty/articles/miller%201997%20protean.DOC
Raichle,
Two views of brain function
Doyle,
Free will: it's a normal biological property, not
a gift or a mystery.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/4591052c
abstract
Julio
Martinez
Voluntary Attention and Working Memory in The Primate Brain: Recording
from
Single Cells
Abstract: Neurons
in the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (dlPFC) of primates respond to
visual
stimuli and are selective for attributes such as location, object
identity and
motion direction (Zaksas and Pasternak, 2006). Furthermore, this
selectivity
persists when stimuli are removed and their attributes maintained in
working
memory. Previous studies have suggested that some dlPFC neurons
preferentially
represent the current sensory input, while others represent the
contents of
working memory (Fuster, 2000; Pasternak and Greenle, 2005). To
investigate this
issue we recorded the spiking activity of 155 dlPFC neurons from two
rhesus
monkeys while they performed different tasks in which they compared the
motion
direction of a sample random-dot pattern to that of a subsequent test
pattern.
In the Memory task, the sample and test presentations were separated by
a delay
period during which the monkey was required to remember the sample
direction.
In the No-memory task, the sample remained present during the entire
trial,
thus eliminating the working memory requirement. For each of the two
tasks, the
ability of each neuron to represent the motion direction of the sample
during the
delay period was quantified using signal detection theory. In
approximately
half of the direction-selective neurons, representations were stronger
when the
sample remained present (No-memory task) than when it was remembered
(Memory
task). Interestingly, in the remaining neurons, the sample direction
was more
strongly encoded when it was remembered than when it remained
perceptually
available. This suggests that while the former neurons preferentially
encode
sensory input, the latter may serve a specific role in working memory
maintenance. The ability of the entire population of recorded neurons
to
represent the sample direction was quantified using a linear
discriminant
analysis. In both tasks classification performance remained well above
chance
throughout the entire delay period. These results demonstrate that in
the dlPFC
the strength of visual representations during working memory is
temporally
robust and comparable to that of representations driven by sensory
input.
Fuster JM. Memory networks in the
prefrontal
cortex. Prog Brain Res.
2000;122:309-16.
Review http://bit.ly/FusterPFC
Zaksas D, Pasternak T. Directional
signals in the prefrontal cortex and in
area MT during a working memory for
visual motion task. J Neurosci. 2006
8;26(45):11726-42. http://www.jneurosci.org/content/26/45/11726.full
Pasternak T, Greenlee MW. Working
memory in primate sensory systems. Nat Rev
Neurosci. 2005 Feb;6(2):97-107.
Review. Erratum in: Nat Rev Neurosci. 2005
6(3):255. http://www.psychology.nottingham.ac.uk/staff/ds1/uploads/Teaching/NatRevNeurosci2005Pasternak.pdf
abstract
Christopher
Pack Vision During Unconsciousness
Abstract: Visual
perception is closely associated with consciousness, and an important
part of
visual perception is the ability to infer the properties of objects
from
time-varying changes in retinal stimulation. Two key properties that
are of
obvious behavioral relevance are their identity and their velocity
relative to
the observer. In this presentation I will review old results that show
how
certain kinds of anesthetics impair the ability of individual neurons
in the
visual cortex to extract important physical quantities from retinal
input. I
will then present more recent work that provides a computational
account of how
these neurons integrate their inputs so as to become selective for
important stimulus
properties. Finally, I will show how the same computations appear to be
at work
in visual cortical regions that are responsible for different
functions,
including the estimation of object identity and velocity.
Mineault, P.J., Khawaja,
F.A., Butts, D.A., and Pack, C.C. (2012) Hierarchical processing of
complex
motion along the primate dorsal visual pathway. Proceedings of the
National
Academy of Sciences of the USA, 109, E972-980. http://packlab.mcgill.ca/mineaultetal2012.pdf
Pack,
C.C., Berezovskii, V.K., and Born, R.T. (2001)
Dynamic properties of neurons in cortical area MT in alert and
anaesthetized
macaque monkeys. Nature, 414, 905-908. http://packlab.mcgill.ca/packetal2001.pdf
abstract
Barbara
Finlay
Continuities/Discontinuities in Vertebrate Brain
Evolution and Cognitive Capacities: Implications for Consciousness?
Abstract: Comparing
the evolution of consciousness and its contents to the structural
evolution of
the brain often runs aground on basic misunderstandings about brain
scaling. Because the neocortex
appears 'oversize'� in humans, for example, the
presumption that the
cortex
must be the structure critical to multiple aspects of human cognition
and
consciousness is ubiquitous.
Demonstration that humans have exactly the relative volume of
cortex
expected for a primate of our brain size demands explicit discussion of
when
discontinuities in awareness should be proposed when no structural
discontinuities exist. When
developmental homologies between vertebrate brain parts are
established, and
the allometries of neurons and networks are well described, true
'discontinuities'�
in brain structure prove to be very rare.
Yet, there are occasional substantial reorganizations of brain
connectivity that may shed light on the contents of consciousness. The reorganization of viscerosensory
representation in insular cortex in large primates may enable basic
changes in
the perception and communication of pain and distress, a phenomenon I
will term 'the pain of altruism'�.
Syal,
S. and Finlay, B.L. (2011) Thinking outside the
cortex: Social motivation in the evolution and development of language.
Developmental Science 14:
417-430 DOI:
10.1111/j.1467-7687.2010.00997.x http://people.psych.cornell.edu/~blf2/pdfs/SyalDS11.pdf
Charvet,
C.J. and Finlay B.L. (2011) Embracing
covariation in brain evolution: Large brains, extended development and
flexible
primate social systems. In
Evolution of the Primate Brain: From Neuron to Behavior, in M.A.Hofman
& D.
Falk, eds., Progress in Brain Research
195: 71-87. http://bit.ly/FinlayBrainEv [PDF will be
provided]
abstract
Gary
Comstock
Feeling Matters
Abstract: What
scientific experiments, if any, are we justified in performing on
animals in
order to answer philosophical questions such as the distribution of
complex
feelings across species? Would researchers, for example, be justified
in
inducing behavioral signs of depression in monkeys if they thought the
results
could help to resolve the metaphysical question, whether nonhumans have
the
capacity to feel, for example, the social anxiety that results from
thinking
that others think you are worthless?
To make progress on this issue, I proceed in three steps. First,
I
review the case for thinking that cynomulgus monkeys experience
social-stress
induced depression, a higher order mental state some humans find worse
than
death. Second, I introduce and rebut three objections to the idea that
we can legitimately
attribute this feeling to monkeys. Third, I conclude by outlining an
invasive
experiment that might help to settle the Distribution Question and I
ask
whether it would be humane to carry it out.
Call, J. & Tomasello, M.,
2008. Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends
in
Cognitive Sciences, 12(5), pp.187-192. http://www.eva.mpg.de/psycho/pdf/Publications_2008_PDF/Call_Tomasello_2008.pdf
Lerner, Y. et al., 2011.
Topographic mapping of a hierarchy of temporal receptive windows using
a
narrated story. The Journal of neuroscience - the official journal of
the Society
for Neuroscience, 31(8), pp.2906-2915. http://neuro.cjb.net/content/31/8/2906.full
Penn, D.C., Holyoak, K.J.
& Povinelli, D.J., 2008. Darwin's Mistake: Explaining the
Discontinuity
Between Human and Nonhuman Minds. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
31(02), pp.109-130.
http://staffwww.dcs.shef.ac.uk/people/A.Sharkey/2008-darwin.pdf
Shively, C.A. et al., 2005.
Social stress-associated depression in adult female cynomolgus monkeys
(Macaca
fascicularis). Biological Psychology, 69(1), pp.67-84.
Stewart, M.E. et al., 2006.
Presentation of Depression in Autism and Asperger Syndrome A Review.
Autism,
10(1), pp.103'116. http://aut.sagepub.com/content/10/1/103.abstract
Willard, S.L. & Shively,
C.A., 2011. Modeling depression in adult female cynomolgus monkeys
(Macaca
fascicularis). American Journal of Primatology, 73, pp.1-15. http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/22076882
abstract
David
Rosenthal
Does
Consciousness Have any Utility?
Abstract: It is
plain that an individual's being conscious and an individual's being
conscious
of various things are both crucial for successful functioning. But it is far less clear how it might
also be useful for a person's psychological states to occur
consciously, as
against those states occurring but without being conscious. I'll restrict attention here to
cognitive and desiderative states, though similar considerations apply
to
perceiving, sensing, and feeling; like cognition and volition, all
these states
are useful; the question is whether any additional utility is conferred
by any
of these states' occurring consciously, and I'll offer reasons to think
not. It has been held that
cognitive and volitional states' being conscious enhances processes of
rational
thought and planning, intentional action, executive function, and the
correction of complex reasoning. I
examine these and related
proposals in the light of empirical findings and theoretical
considerations,
and conclude that there is little reason to think that any additional
utility
results from these states' occurring consciously.
If
so, we cannot rely on evolutionary adaptation to
explain why such states so often occur consciously in humans and likely
many
other animals. Elsewhere
(Consciousness and Mind, Clarendon, 2005) I have briefly sketched an
alternative
explanation, on which cognitive and desiderative states come to be
conscious as
a byproduct of other useful psychological developments, some involving
language. But there is still no
significant utility that these states' being conscious adds to the
utility of
those other developments.
Rosenthal,
D "Consciousness and Its Function"
Neuropsychologia, 46, 3 (2008): 829-840.
https://wfs.gc.cuny.edu/DRosenthal/www/DR-func.pdf
abstractMark
Balaguer A
Scientifically Reputable Version of
Indeterministic Libertarian Free Will
Abstract: In this
paper, I defend libertarianism (i.e., the view that humans have
libertarian
free will) against philosophical and scientific objections. The main philosophical objection is
sometimes called the Mind argument, or the luck objection; in
responding to
this objection, I argue that there's a certain subset of our decisions
that
have the following property: if they are undetermined in the right way,
then
they are libertarian free. This
conclusion turns the traditional Mind argument upside-down; if my
argument is
cogent, then it shows that the question of whether we possess
libertarian free
will reduces to an empirical question about whether certain of our
decisions
are undetermined in the right way.
Finally, in the second half of the paper, I respond to a few
scientific
objections to libertarianism, arguing that we do not have any good
empirical
reasons to doubt the hypothesis that our decisions are undetermined in
the
right way. Now, it seems clear
that we also don't have any good reason to believe this hypothesis, and
so my
overall conclusion is that the question of whether we possess
libertarian free
will is an open empirical question.
Balaguer, M. Free Will as an
Open Scientific Problem, MIT Press, 2010. http://mitpress.mit.edu/books/chapters/0262013541chap1.pdf
Balaguer, M. "Why There
are no Good Arguments for any Interesting Version of Determinism,"
Synthese, vol. 168 (2009), pp. 1-21. http://www.calstatela.edu/faculty/mbalagu/papers/Why_there_are_no_good_arguments_for_determinism.pdf#view=FitH,top
Balaguer, M. "A
Coherent, Naturalistic, and Plausible Formulation of Libertarian Free
Will," Nous, vol. 38 (September 2004), pp. 379-406. http://www.calstatela.edu/faculty/mbalagu/papers/A%20Coherent,%20Naturalistic,%20and%20Plausible%20Formulation%20of%20Libertarian%20Free%20Will.pdf#view=FitH,top
abstract
Adrian Ward Mind
Blanking: When the Stream of Consciousness Runs Dry
Abstract: Is it possible for the mind to
be blank? Conscious thought is central to human experience, and this
centrality
has led many to propose that the stream of consciousness is
uninterrupted -
that 'thought is�without breach, crack, or
division' (James,
1892). We propose
that these presumptions of omnipresence are premature, and explore the
phenomenon of 'mind-blanking,' a mental state defined by a lack of
conscious
thought. Using experimental evidence from several studies, we present
the case
that (1) mind-blanking is a distinct mental state, distinguishable from
both
stimulus-dependent thought and other stimulus-independent mental states
such as
mind-wandering; (2) mind-blanking is subject to ironic effects of
mental
control, such that attempts to suppress blanking result in more
blanking than
if suppression had never been attempted; and (3) mind-blanking is
subject to
ego depletion effects, such that ego-depleting activities result in
higher
incidences of blanking during a subsequent free thought period.
Blackmore,
S. (2002) There is no stream of consciousness. ournal of Consciousness
Studies,
Volume 9, number 5-6 http://www.susanblackmore.co.uk/Articles/jcs02.htm
Jonathan
W. Schooler (2002) Re-representing consciousness: dissociations between
experience and meta- consciousness. TRENDS in Cognitive Sciences Vol.6
No.8
http://bernardbaars.pbworks.com/f/Schooler%2B-%2BRe-representing%2Bcsns%2B-%2BTICS2002.pdf
abstract
Simon
Baron-Cohen
Evolution
of Empathy
Abstract: Empathy
is the drive to identify another person's thoughts and feelings and to
respond
to these with an appropriate emotion. Empathy comes by degrees, with
individual
differences evident in the traditional bell curve. We now know quite a
lot
about which parts of the brain are used when we empathize and how
empathy
develops in children. We also know that early experience affects
empathy, but
so does biology: hormones in the womb, and specific genes. There are
several
ways in which one can lose one's empathy, clearly seen in psychiatric
conditions such as the personality disorders, including the psychopath.
We
discuss how people with autism and psychopaths show opposite empathy
profiles.
Finally, the discovery that there may be 'genes for empathy' implies
that
empathy may be the result of our evolution.
Baron-Cohen,
S, (2011) Zero Degrees of Empathy: A new
theory of human cruelty. Penguin/Basic Books. http://www.amazon.co.uk/Zero-Degrees-Empathy-Simon-Baron-Cohen/dp/0141017961
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Aq_nCTGSfWE
http://www.autismresearchcentre.com
Baron-Cohen, S (2003) The
Essential Difference: men, women, and the extreme male brain.
Penguin/Basic
Books
http://www.thetransporters.com
Baron-Cohen, S (2009) Autism
and Asperger Syndrome: The Facts. Oxford University Press.
http://www.jkp.com/mindreading
Simon Baron-Cohen and Sally
Wheelwright The Empathy Quotient: An Investigation of Adults with
Asperger
Syndrome or High Functioning Autism, and Normal Sex Differences.
Journal of
Autism and Developmental Disorders, Vol. 34, No. 2, April 2004 http://gamut.neiu.edu/~lruecker/baron-cohen.pdf
abstract Alfred
Mele Do
Conscious Decisions Ever Play a Role in Action
Production?
Abstract: I will
discuss some alleged evidence (from Libet, for example) that conscious
intentions never play a role in producing corresponding actions and
some
alleged evidence (from studies of implementation intentions) that they
sometimes do play this role. I
then take up the question whether conscious reasoning ever plays a role
in the
production of intentions and actions.
I set the stage for my discussion by rehearsing a familiar
scientific
argument for the claim that free will is an illusion.
Mele:
Intentional action: Controversies, data, and core
hypotheses
http://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/download?doi=10.1.1.3.2117&rep=rep1&type=pdf
Mele/Cushman:
Intentional Action, Folk Judgments, and
Stories: Sorting Things Out
http://www.wjh.harvard.edu/~cushman/publications/Publications_files/mele%26cushman_200 7.pdf
Mele:
Effective Intentions (Oxford University Press,
2009) chapters 3, 4, and 7 http://bit.ly/MeleFreeWill
Mele:
Free will: Action theory meets neuroscience
http://www.unisi.it/eventi/practical_philosophy/paper/Mele.pdf
Mele:
Real Self-Deception http://cogprints.org/295/1/MELE.html
abstract
Hakwan
Lau How to
study the functions of subjective awareness?
Abstract: I give
some examples of subliminal priming studies suggesting that subjective
awareness may not be as functionally powerful as we might think.
However these
studies as well as most others in the field suffer from a
methodological
problem: in rendering stimuli unconscious we substantially lower the
relevant
signal strength, so subliminal priming effects are invariably weak. It
is a
problem for a whole field to rely on weak effects because null results
are hard
to interpret and positive results are subject to selection and
publication
bias. So I propose a new approach to address this problem. The key is
to keep
signal strength / perceptual sensitivity constant while manipulating
subjective
awareness, and to see how that affects cognitive functions. This is
hard to
achieve but I show preliminary data demonstrating how this could be
done.
Unconscious
activation of the cognitive control system
in the human prefrontal cortex. Lau HC, Passingham RE. J Neurosci. 2007
May
23;27(21):5805-11.
http://neuro.cjb.net/content/27/21/5805.full
Empirical
support for higher-order theories of conscious
awareness
Hakwan Lau and David Rosenthal
Attention
to Intention http://www.fil.ion.ucl.ac.uk/~hclau/Lau_2004_Science.pdf
Subliminal
stimuli in the near absence of attention
influence top-down cognitive control.
Rahnev DA, Huang E, Lau H. Atten
Percept Psychophys. 2012
Does
response interference depend on the subjective
visibility of flanker distractors?
Maniscalco
B, Bang JW, Iravani L, Camps-Febrer F, Lau H. Atten Percept Psychophys.
2012
Attention
induces conservative subjective biases in
visual perception. Rahnev D, Maniscalco B, Graves T, Huang E, de Lange
FP, Lau
H. Nat Neurosci. 2011 Oct 23;14(12):1513-5
Direct
injection of noise to the visual cortex decreases
accuracy but increases decision confidence. Rahnev DA, Maniscalco B,
Luber B,
Lau H, Lisanby SH. J Neurophysiol. 2012 Mar;107(6):1556-63.
abstract
Luiz
Pessoa
Cognitive-Emotional Interactions
Abstract: The
current view of brain organization supports the notion that there is a
considerable degree of functional specialization and that many regions
can be
conceptualized as either 'affective' or 'cognitive'. Popular examples
are the
amygdala in the domain of emotion and the lateral prefrontal cortex in
cognition. This prevalent view is problematic for a number of reasons.
It will
be argued that complex cognitive-emotional behaviors have their basis
in
networks of brain areas, none of which should be conceptualized as
specifically
affective or cognitive. Central to cognitive-emotional interactions are
brain
areas with a high degree of connectivity called hubs, which are
critical for
regulating the flow and integration of information between regions. To
illustrate cognitive-emotional processing, I will discuss a series of
studies
that have investigated interactions between emotion and perception, and
emotion
and executive function. In the final part of my talk, I will address
the
following question: What is the relationship between emotion and
consciousness?
I will discuss how large-scale interactions are critical for both
emotion-cognition
and consciousness, suggesting that the study of these interactions is
needed
for advancing our understanding of their relationship.
Pessoa, L. On the
relationship between emotion and cognition. Nature Reviews Neuroscience
2008.
Feb;9(2):148-58. http://lce.umd.edu/publications_files/Pessoa_NRN_2008.pdf
Tsuchiya N, Adolphs R.
Emotion and consciousness. Trends Cogn Sci, 2007 Apr;11(4):158-67
http://emotion.caltech.edu/papers/TsuchiyaAdolphs2007Emotion.pdf
Thompson, E. & Varela, F.
J. Radical embodiment: neural
dynamics and consciousness. Trends Cogn. Sci. 5, 418–425 (2001).
http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S1364661300017502
abstract
Marthe
Kiley-Worthington Comparing Elephant and Equine Mental
Traits,
Subjectivity and
Consciousness
Abstract: A
combination of both reviewed scientific knowledge and knowledge
gathered from
philosophy of mind, critically assessed anecdotes & centuries of
folk
knowledge concerning the cognition of other mammals (Conditional
Anthropomorphism) is proposed as a rational method to begin to outline
these
species subjectivity & consciousness. This paper briefly examines
mammalian
similarities and species differences in bodies & behaviour (
sensations,
feelings, emotions learning, ecological and social knowledge,
rationality,
dreaming & imagination, awareness of self, theory of mind &
comprehension of human language) , their
probable resulting mental attitudes, subjectivity and type of
consciousness. Such an approach allows a greater understanding of
another
species consciousness, and can, perhaps, enrich our own.
A comparative study of equine
and elephant mental attributes leading to an acceptance of their
subjectivity
and consciousness . M.Kiley-Worthington. Journal of
Consciousness Exploration & Research Jan
2011 vol 2 p 10-50. http://jcer.com/index.php/jcj/article/view/126
Behavioural Problems of Farm
Animals. http://www.cabdirect.org/abstracts/19770131707.html;jsessionid=446799673DE05414208BBBB4C817B7AA
Animals in circuses and zoos:
Chiron's world http://www.cabdirect.org/abstracts/19912259033.html
abstract
Axel
Cleermans
Consciousness and Learning
Abstract: Here,
starting from the fact that neural activity is intrinsically
unconscious, I
suggest that consciousness arises as a result of the brain's continuous
attempts at predicting not only the consequences of action on the world
and on
other agents, but also the consequences of activity in one cerebral
region on
activity in other regions. By this account, the brain continuously and
unconsciously learns to redescribe its own activity to itself, so
developing
systems of metarepresentations that characterize and qualify their
target
representations. Such re-representations form the basis of conscious
experience, and also subtend successful control of action. In a sense
thus,
this is the enactive perspective, but turned both inwards and further
outwards.
Consciousness amounts to 'signal detection on the mind'; it is the
brain's
(non-conceptual, embodied, implicit) theory about itself. By this
hypothesis,
which I call the "radical plasticity thesis", consciousness
critically depends on a cognitive system's ability to learn about (1)
the
effects of its actions on the environment, (2) the effects of its
actions on
other agents, and on (3) the effects of activity in one cerebral region
on
other cerebral regions.
Cleeremans,
A. (2011). The Radical Plasticity Thesis:
How the brain learns to be conscious. Frontiers in Psychology, 2, 1-12.
http://srsc.ulb.ac.be/axcwww/papers/pdf/07-PBR.pdf
Timmermans,
B., Schilbach, L., Pasquali, A., &
Cleeremans, A. (2012).
Higher-order thoughts in action:
Consciousness as an unconscious redescription process Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society B
http://rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org/content/367/1594/1412.short
Pasquali,
A., Timmermans, B., & Cleeremans,
A.(2010).
Know thyself: Metacognitive
networks and measures of consciousness
Cognition, 117 182-190 http://srsc.ulb.ac.be/axcwww/papers/pdf/10-COG.pdf
abstract
Stefano
Mancuso
Evolution of Plant Intelligence
Abstract:
Intelligent behavior is a complex adaptive phenomenon that has evolved
to
enable organisms to deal with variable environmental circumstances.
Maximizing
fitness requires skill in foraging for necessary resources (food) in
competitive circumstances and is probably the activity in which
intelligent
behavior is most easily seen. Biologists suggest that intelligence
encompasses
the characteristics of detailed sensory perception, information
processing,
learning, memory, choice, optimisation of resource sequestration with
minimal
outlay, self-recognition, and foresight by predictive modeling. All
these
properties are concerned with a capacity for problem solving in
recurrent and
novel situations. I will review the evidence that individual plant
species
exhibit all of these intelligent behavioral capabilities but do so
through
phenotypic plasticity, not movement. Furthermore it is in the
competitive
foraging for resources that most of these intelligent attributes have
been
detected. Plants should therefore be regarded as prototypical
intelligent
organisms, a concept that has considerable consequences for
investigations of
whole plant communication, computation and signal transduction.
It
should not be surprising that neuronal computation is not limited to
animal brains
but is used also by bacteria and plants. It is generally assumed that
brains
and neurons represent late evolutionary achievements which are present
only in
more advanced animals. But recent data suggest that our understanding
of
bacteria, unicellular eukaryotic organisms, plants, brains and neurons,
rooted
in Aristotelian philosophy is flawed. Neural aspects of biological
systems are
obvious already in bacteria and unicellular biological units such as
sexual
gametes and diverse unicellular eukaryotic organisms. Altogether,
processes and
activities thought to represent evolutionarily 'recent' specializations
of the
nervous system may be ancient and fundamental cell survival processes.
Mindless
mastery - Nature 2002 http://www.linv.org/images/about_pdf/Nature%202002%20Trewavas.pdf
Aspects
of Plant Intelligence - Annals pf Botany 2003 http://www.linv.org/images/about_pdf/Ann%20Bot%202003%20Trewavas.pdf
Plant
intelligence - Naturwissenschaften 2005 http://www.linv.org/images/about_pdf/Naturwissenschaften%202005%20Trewavas.pdf
Green
plants as intelligent organisms - TRENDS in Plant
Science 2005 http://www.linv.org/images/about_pdf/Trends%202005%20Trewavas.pdf
Plant
Neurobiology as a Paradigm Shift Not Only in the
Plant Sciences http://www.linv.org/images/about_pdf/Plant%20Signaling%20&%20Behavior%20%202007%20F.pdf
Plant
neurobiology: no brain, no gain? - TRENDS in Plant
Science 2007 http://www.linv.org/images/about_pdf/Trends%202007%20Alpi.pdf
Response
to Alpi et al.: Plant neurobiology: the gain is
more than the name - TRENDS in Plant Science 2007 http://www.linv.org/images/about_pdf/Trends%202007%20Brenner.pdf
Response
to Alpi et al.: Plant neurobiology - all
metaphors have value - TRENDS in Plant Science 2007 http://www.linv.org/images/about_pdf/Trends%202007%20Trewavas.pdf
Reflections
on 'plant neurobiology' - BioSystems 2008 http://www.linv.org/images/about_pdf/BioSystems%202008%20Barlow.pdf
Plant
neurobiology: from sensory biology, via plant
communication, to social plant behavior - Cognitive Process 2009 http://www.linv.org/images/about_pdf/Cognitive%20processing%202008.pdf
Spatiotemporal
dynamics of the electrical network
activity in the root apex - Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences
2009 http://www.linv.org/images/about_pdf/PNAS%202009%20Masi.pdf
Deep
evolutionary origins of neurobiology - Communicative
& Integrative Biology 2009 http://www.linv.org/images/about_pdf/Communicative%20Integrative%20Biology%20%202009%20.pdf
abstract
Gualtiero
Piccinini
Is Consciousness a Spandrel?
Abstract: Assigning
a biological function to phenomenal consciousness appears to be needed
to
explain its evolutionary origin. For evolution by natural selection
operates on
organisms' traits based on the functions they fulfill. And yet
identifying the
function(s) of phenomenal consciousness has proven difficult. Some have
proposed that the function of phenomenal consciousness is facilitating
mental
processes such as learning or reasoning. But mental processes such as
learning
and reasoning seem to be possible in the absence of phenomenal
consciousness.
It is difficult to pinpoint in what way phenomenal consciousness
enhances such
processes. In this paper, we explore a possibility that has been
neglected to
date. Perhaps phenomenal consciousness is a spandrel, that is, a
byproduct of
other traits that has no functions of its own. If so, then phenomenal
consciousness has an evolutionary explanation even though it fulfills
no biological
function.
S.
J. Gould and R. C. Lewontin (1979), 'The Spandrels of
San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist
Programme,' Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B 205, 581-598.
http://www.jc.edu/users/jensen/spandrels%20of%20san%20marcos.pdf
abstract
Malcolm
MacIver
Sensory and Motor Spaces and the Emergence of
Multiple Futures
Abstract: Back in
our watery days as fish, we lived in a medium that was inherently
unfriendly to
seeing things very far away. The technical way this is measured is the
"attenuation length" of light through the medium. After light travels
the attenuation length through a medium, about 63% of the light is
blocked. The
attenuation length of light in water is on the order of tens of meters.
For a
beast of a meter or two in length, which moves at a rate of about a
body length
or two per second, that's a pretty short horizon of time and space. In
just a
few seconds, you'll reach the edge of where you were able to see. If
you're
down in the depths at all, or in less clear water, you may reach the
edge of
your perceptual horizon in about a second. In this talk, I'll explore
the
quantification of sensory and motor spaces, developed through our work
on the
weakly electric fish, a popular model system of sensory neurobiology. I
discuss
the relationship between behavioral control and the relative size of
these
spaces. Finally, I'll discuss whether emergence on to land, where the
attenuation length of light is essentially infinite, may have been a
key step
in producing favorable conditions for the evolution of the ability to
plan over
multiple possible futures.
Why
Did Consciousness Evolve, and How Can We Modify It? http://blogs.discovermagazine.com/sciencenotfiction/2011/03/14/why-did-consciousness-evolve-and-how-can-we-modify-it/
Neuroethology
From Morphological Computation to Planning
http://www.neuromech.northwestern.edu/publications/MacI09a/MacI09a.pdf
Omnidirectional
Sensory and Motor Volumes in Electric
Fish
http://www.neuromech.northwestern.edu/publications/Snyd07a/Snyd07a.pdf
abstract
Jennifer
Mather
Evolutionary Pressures and Cephalopod Consciousness
Abstract: On the
face of it, cephalopods are unlikely candidates for consciousness, even
at a
primary level. They stem from
slow, simple molluscan ancestors, but during evolution they have lost
the
protective shell. Likely in
the competition with bony fishes, they have instead developed a
centralized
brain, acute vision, complex control of arm movement and a stunning
skin
display system. But unlike other
non-human animals with well developed cognition, they are not social. What would the evolutionary pressure
be, then, for these animals to develop consciousness?
The answer may lie in the complexity of their near-shore
marine environment. Mobile
cephalopods must search this environment to find prey, and octopuses do
so with
a saltatory search technique.
At the same time they are vulnerable to predators and have an
array of
defenses, from camouflage to false eye spots and ink release to flight,
to
avoid or react to them. Yet they
are mobile—octopuses move to a new home range every ten days or
two
weeks—so they cannot store information and responses to form
automatic
loops. It may be this constant
change and pressure to update that caused the cephalopods to develop a
simple
form of consciousness.
Mather,
J. A. (2008). Cephalopod consciousness:
Behavioral evidence. Consciousness and
Cognition, 17, 37-48
http://www.mendeley.com/research/cephalopod-consciousness-behavioural-evidence/#page-1
Mather,
J. A. (2010). What might consciousness in
cephalopods be like? Journal of
Cosmology (special issue on consciousness) http://journalofcosmology.com/Consciousness113.html
Philosophical
background of attitudes toward and
treatment of invertebrates http://research.tamucc.edu/compliance/iacuc/PDF/ILAR%20Journal.pdf#page=91
Behavioural
indicators of pain in crustacean decapods http://www.scielosp.org/scielo.php?pid=S0021-25712009000400013&script=sci_arttext
Pain
and suffering in invertebrates? http://www.vliz.be/imisdocs/publications/231732.pdf
New
evidence of animal consciousness http://postcog.ucd.ie/files/fulltext.pdf
[See also David Edelman reference list]
abstract Eva
Jablonka
Evolutionary Origins of Experiencing
Abstract: An
approach focused on the evolutionary transition to experiencing
– to
the
first organisms with phenomenal consciousness – can enable the
identification of fundamental
organizational principles involved in experiencing. Based on the
heuristics of
the origin-of-life research, we outline a parallel approach to
experiencing,
and suggest that just as function emerged with the transition to life,
felt-needs emerged with the transition to experiencing. We argue that
experiencing is a facet of open-ended associative learning in neural
animals
with a CNS, and that the evolution of associative learning was a key
factor in
the metazoan diversification during the Cambrian. It endowed animals
with
motivation and increased their discrimination powers on the basis of
systemic
reward systems. Tracking the molecular and neural correlates of
associative
learning as they emerged during evolutionary history may therefore shed
light
on the dynamics that underlie elementary forms of experiencing.
Simona
Ginsburg and Eva Jablonka (2010) Experiencing: a
Jamesian approach Journal of
Consciousness Studies 17:102-124. http://www.openu.ac.il/Personal_sites/download/Simona-Ginsburg/Experiencing-A-Jamesian-Approach2010.pdf
Simona
Ginsburg and Eva Jablonka (2007) The Transition
to Experiencing: I. Limited Learning and Limited Experiencing Biological Theory. 2(3) 218–230.
Simona
Ginsburg and Eva Jablonka (2007) The Transition
to Experiencing: II. The Evolution of Associative Learning Based on
Feelings.
Biological Theory 2(3) 231–243
Simona
Ginsburg and Eva Jablonka (2010) Associative
learning: a factor in the Cambrian explosion. Journal of Theoretical
Biology
266:11–20.
abstract
Alain
Ptito
Neural Mechanisms of Blindsight after Hemispherectomy: Tapping into the
Unconscious
Abstract: Hemispherectomy
subjects (Hs) have offered a unique opportunity to study the role that
subcortical structures play in blindsight because the hemisphere
contralateral
to the blind field is absent or non-functional. We first showed Hs
could detect
and localize simple targets and moving gratings, discriminate grating
velocity
and differentiate forms in their blind field. We suggested a role of
subcortical
pathways i.e. the superior colliculi (SC), with the participation of
the
remaining hemisphere. We reported the existence of residual vision with
awareness in the blind field and showed that Hs were insensitive to
motion-in-depth in their hemianopic field and that some possess
blindsight as
shown by a spatial summation effect i.e. subjects only react to the
stimulus
presented in their intact field, without being aware that the
simultaneous
presentation of another stimulus in their blind field lowers their
reaction
time. We hypothesized that this indirect method to evaluate blindsight
could
involve subcortical mechanisms without requiring cortical processing,
and
without the subject's awareness. We then reported that the cellular
integrity
and metabolism of the ipsilateral SC in the vervet monkey are much less
affected than those of the dorsal lateral geniculate nucleus (dLGN)
after
neonatal hemispherectomy. We underlined the importance of controlling
intraocular light scatter and published the first fMRI study on
residual
vision. We concluded that the SC are likely implicated in blindsight in
Hs, and
we recently utilized the color vision properties of collicular cells to
demonstrate its involvement in the residual visual abilities of Hs.
Since the
primate SC does not receive retinal input from shortwave-sensitive (S-)
cones
involved in colour vision, consequently rendering them colour blind to
blue
yellow stimuli, we tested 3 Hs who had reliably shown blindsight. They
demonstrated a spatial summation effect only to achromatic stimuli
suggesting
that their blindsight is colour-blind to blue/yellow stimuli and is not
receiving input from retinal S-cones. We concluded that blindsight is
likely
mediated by the SC in Hs. We were the first to use Diffusion Tensor
Imaging
(DTI) Tractography to investigate pulvinar connectivity in humans and
SC
connectivity in Hs with and without blindsight. We demonstrated the
presence of
projections from the ipsi- and contralesional SC to primary visual
areas,
visual association areas, precentral areas/FEF and the internal capsule
of the
remaining hemisphere in Hs with 'Type
I' or 'attention-blindsight' and an
absence of these connections in Hs without it. In another study using
fMRI, we
demonstrated in Hs that achromatic stimuli but not S-cone-isolating
stimuli in
the blind field of a subject with blindsight activated visual areas
FEF/ V5 and
that the cortical activation pattern was enhanced by achromatic stimuli
only.
We concluded that the human SC is blind to S-cone-isolating stimuli,
and that
blindsight is mediated by an S-cone-independent collicular pathway, at
least in
Hs.
The
SC is the main recipient of retinal projections in
lower mammals with a phylogenetically older and more primitive visual
system
than humans. Similar but weaker retinocollicular projections also exist
in
humans. Although existing SC connections to the remaining cortical
areas seem
to play a pivotal role in unconscious vision, blindsight subjects
remain
unaware of the information processed in their blind visual field. One
possibility for the lack of awareness may lie in the lack of
synchronicity in
cerebral activation. The human visual pathways process information
simultaneously and yet are able to work independently of each other (as
is the
case following a circumscribed lesion in a visual cortical area). For
conscious
perception, however, a specific synchronized activation pattern of
different
cortical areas involving ventral, parietal and frontal visual areas is
believed
to be crucial. Our results indicate that Hs with 'Type I' or'attention
blindsight' are able to enhance visual performance in their blind
field, but
remain unaware of visual processing presumably because they are unable
to access
a more complex synchronous cortical activation pattern involving higher
top-down mechanisms necessary for conscious vision.
Neural
substrates of blindsight after hemispherectomy http://unfweb.criugm.qc.ca/jdoyon/cours_6032/Neuroscientist%202007.pdf
Unconscious
vision: new insights into the neuronal
correlate of blindsight using diffusion tractography http://brain.oxfordjournals.org/content/129/7/1822.full
Neural
Substrates of Blindsight in Hemispherectomized
Subjects. http://www.bic.mni.mcgill.ca/~sandra/pdfs/Review_2007.pdf
The
nature of consciousness in the visually deprived
brain http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3111253/
abstract
Amir
Shmuel
Neurophysiological and hemodynamic measurements of spontaneous activity
and
functional connectivity
Abstract: Recent
functional MRI (fMRI) studies in humans have demonstrated large
amplitude slow
(< 0.1 Hz) fluctuations in the resting state. Importantly, these
spontaneous
fluctuations in the Blood-Oxygenation-Level-Dependent (BOLD) signal are
often
synchronized over distant parts of the brain, a phenomenon termed
resting-state
functional connectivity. Functional connectivity analysis identifies
resting-state networks of areas that also coactivate in response to
stimuli or
tasks. In my talk, I'll first explore whether fMRI-measured spontaneous
fluctuations reflect those seen in neurophysiological activity. I will
then
demonstrate that resting-state functional connectivity exists in a
hierarchical
manner in space. In addition to the commonly reported networks on the
spatial
scale of cortical areas, smaller networks can be observed at the
resolution
scales of sub-areas and cortical columns. I will conclude with
hypotheses on
the mechanisms involved, the role of spontaneous activity, and
implications for
clinical neuroscience.
Smith
et al., 2009 Correspondence of the brain's
functional architecture during activation and rest http://www.pnas.org/content/106/31/13040.full
abstract
Gilles
Plourde
General Anesthetics for the Study Consciousness
Abstract: Although
general anesthetics have been used for more than 150 years and suppress
consciousness in a predictable manner, their mechanisms of action are
not fully
elucidated. Numerous studies have been devoted to understanding how
general
anesthetics impair consciousness in human subjects using either
functional
brain imaging or electrophysiology. These studies have obvious
relevance for
the study of consciousness, particularly for consciousness as a waking
state
and in regard to self-awareness. They have revealed the critical
involvement of
the thalamus and offered evidence supporting the hypothesis that the
anesthetized state is associated with loss of connectivity and
attenuation
neuronal oscillations in the high-gamma range. In this lecture, I will
first
review the aspect of the pharmacology of general anesthetic that are
essential
to appreciate the possibilities that these drugs offer to study
consciousness
as well as their limitations. In the second part, I will summarize the
main
findings that emerge from the literature.
Alkire MT, Hudetz AG, Tononi
G. Consciousness and anesthesia. Science 2008; 322: 876-80 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2743249/
Franks NP. General
anaesthesia: from molecular targets to neuronal pathways of sleep and
arousal.
Nat Rev Neurosci 2008; 9: 370-86 http://hopecenterdev.wustl.edu/training/bio5663/Documents/FRANKS_NATNEUROSCI_rev.pdf
Critical involvement of the
thalamus and precuneus during restoration of consciousness with
physostigmine
in humans during propofol anaesthesia: a positron emission tomography
study http://bja.oxfordjournals.org/content/106/4/548.full
abstract
Amir
Raz
Hypnosis as Experimental Tool to Study Metacognition, Causality and
Volition
Abstract: An early
form of psychotherapy, hypnosis has been tarnished by a checkered
history:
stage shows, movies and cartoons that perpetuate specious myths; and
individuals who unabashedly write 'hypnotist' on their business cards.
Hypnosis
is in the twilight zone alongside a few other mind–body
exemplars.
Although scientists are still unraveling how hypnosis works, little is
mystical
about this powerful top-down process, which is an important tool in the
armamentarium of the cognitive scientist seeking to unlock topical
conundrums. Philosophical research
has revealed a great deal about three categories of behavior: conscious
decision-making, authorship, and sense of control. However, little
conclusive
evidence regarding their interdependent nature has been found, due to
the
difficulties in separating their influences on tasks such as
decision-making.
Demacheva,
I, M Ladouceur, E Steinberg, G Pogossova, A
Raz (2012) The Applied Cognitive Psychology of Attention: A Step Closer
to
Understanding Magic Tricks. Applied Cognitive Psychology http://www.jgh.ca/uploads/Psychiatry/Articles%20PDF/Magic1-Published.pdf
Raz,
A. (2011). Does Neuroimaging of Suggestion
Elucidate Hypnotic Trance? International Journal of Clinical and
Experimental
Hypnosis, 59(3), 363-377. http://www.jgh.ca/uploads/Psychiatry/Articles%20PDF/IJCEH2011.pdf
Raz,
A (2011) Hypnosis: a twilight zone of the top-down
variety. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, December 2011, Vol. 15, No. 12 http://psycho.unibas.ch/fileadmin/psycho/redaktion/Abteilungen/Klinische_Psychologie_und_Psychotherapie/Raz_2011_TINS.pdf
Raz,
A., & Whatley, B. (2009) Consciousness reduced:
Will neuroscience confine the mind to the brain? PsycCRITIQUES -
Contemporary
Psychology, 54(39). http://www.jgh.ca/uploads/Psychiatry/Articles%20PDF/PSYCCRITIQUES_consciousness_reduced.pdf
Raz,
A., & Zigman, P., (2009). Using Magic as a
Vehicle to Elucidate Attention. In A. Finazzi Agr˜ et al. (Eds.),
Encyclopedia
of Life Sciences. London: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.
http://www.jgh.ca/uploads/Psychiatry/Articles%20PDF/Magic_vehicle_Raz_zigman_2009.pdf
Raz,
A. (2009) Varieties of Attention: A
Research-Magician's Perspective. In G. Bernston and J. Cacioppo (Eds.),
Handbook of Neuroscience for the Behavioural Sciences (pp. 361-369).
Hoboken:
John Wiley and Sons, Inc. http://bit.ly/RazHypno
abstract
John
Searle
Consciousness and Causality
Abstract: How
do neurobiological processes in the brain cause consciousness? I think
this is
the most important question in the biological sciences today. Two
related
questions: Where exactly is consciousness realized in the brain and how
does it
function causally in our behavior? We know consciousness happens and we
know
the brain does it. How does it work? How do we approach this problem
scientifically? The standard way is to go through three steps. First,
try to
find the neurobiological correlate of consciousness. Second, try to
test if the
correlations are in fact causal. Do the neurobiological states cause
consciousness?
Third, try to formulate a theory. Why do these processes cause
consciousness at
all, and why do these specific processes cause these specific conscious
states?
One depressing feature of this entire research project is that it does
not seem
to be making much progress.
Mystery of consciousness
a book by me. NYRB book
http://files.meetup.com/227880/The%20Mystery%20of%20Consciousness.doc
The Problem of Consciousness:
http://users.ecs.soton.ac.uk/harnad/Papers/Py104/searle.prob.html
How to study consciousness
scientifically
http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1692422/pdf/9854266.pdf
Free Will as a Problem in
Neurobiology
http://philonantes.free.fr/Searle_Free_Will_as_a_Problem_in_Neurobiology.pdf